Talbott's Universalism Once More
William Lane Craig
William Lane Craig
is Research Professor of Philosophy at Talbot School of Theology
in La Mirada, California. He lives in Atlanta, Georgia, with
his wife Jan and their two teenage children Charity and John.
At the age of sixteen as a junior in high school, he first heard
the message of the Christian gospel and yielded his life to Christ.
Dr. Craig pursued his undergraduate studies at Wheaton College
(B.A. 1971) and graduate studies at Trinity Evangelical Divinity
School (M.A. 1974; M.A. 1975), the University of Birmingham (England)
(Ph.D. 1977), and the University of Munich (Germany) (D.Theol.
1984). From 1980-86 he taught Philosophy of Religion at Trinity,
during which time he and Jan started their family. In 1987 they
moved to Brussels, Belgium, where Dr. Craig pursued research
at the University of Louvain until 1994.
In the debate between universalism and particularism,
three questions need to be addressed: (I) Has it been shown that
it is inconsistent to affirm both that God is omniscient, omnipotent,
and omnibenevolent and that some persons do not receive Christ
and are damned? (II) Can these two affirmations be shown to be
consistent? (III) Is it plausible that both affirmations are
true? In this on-going debate with Thomas Talbott, I argue that
Talbott has failed to show the above affirmations to be inconsistent,
that while one cannot prove them to be consistent, it is plausible
that they are, and that it is also plausible that both affirmations
are in fact true.
"Talbott's Universalism Once More." Religious
Studies 29 (1993): 297-308.
See also Talbott's
Universalism.
NOTE: Dr. Craig uses logic symbols in this
document. For users with Macintosh computer systems, for best
results please set your browser to view this document using Western
MacRoman encoding. In Netscape 3, use Options | Encoding and
choose Western MacRoman. For Netscape 4, use View | Encoding
and choose Western MacRoman.
Introduction
In my No Other Name,{1}
I asserted that detractors of Christian exclusivism are, in effect,
posing a soteriological problem of evil, to wit, that the proposition
1. God is omniscient, omnipotent, and omnibenevolent
is inconsistent with the proposition
2. Some persons do not receive Christ and are damned.
Following the strategy of the Free Will Defense, I pointed
out that if (1) and (2) are to be shown to be broadly logically
inconsistent, then the anti-exclusivist must furnish some additional
premiss(es) which meets the following conditions: (i) its conjunction
with (1) and (2) formally entails a contradiction, (ii) it is
either necessarily true, essential to theism, or a logical consequence
of propositions that are, and (iii) its meeting conditions (i)
and (ii) could not be rationally denied by a right-thinking person.
These are very exigent conditions, and I confessed that I was
"not aware of anyone who has tried to supply the missing
premise which meets these conditions."{2}
Within a year, Thomas Talbott published his independently
developed critique of Christian exclusivism in which he attempted
to do just that.{3} The
missing premiss is
(P3) Necessarily, God loves a person S (with a perfect form of love) at
a time t only if God's intention at t and every
moment subsequent to t is to do everything within his
power to promote supremely worthwhile happiness in S,
provided that the actions taken are consistent with his promoting
the same kind of happiness in all others whom he also loves.
(P3) in conjunction with (1) entails
3. For any created person S and time t subsequent
to the creation of S, God's intention at t is to
do all he properly can to promote supremely worthwhile happiness
in S,
and (3) is contradictory to
4. There is a person S and a time t subsequent
to the creation of S such that it is not God's intention
at t to do all that he properly can to promote supremely
worthwhile happiness in S,
which is entailed by Talbott's
5. God will irrevocably reject some persons and subject those
persons to everlasting punishment,
which Talbott would say is entailed by my (2). In accordance
with condition (iii) above, Talbott must regard the truth of
(P3) as rationally undeniable by a right-thinking
person, and so also the entailment of (4) by (5) and (5) by (2).
Now in my response to Talbott,{4}
I denied that Talbott had proven that the conjunction of (1),
(P3), and (5) formally entails a contradiction,
and I questioned the truth of (P3). More
than that, I recalled arguments from my original piece intended
to show that (1) and (5) are consistent and, moreover, even plausibly
true.
This brief review is necessary because in his most recent
contribution to the debate{5}
Talbott subtly shifts the burden of proof from his own shoulders
to those of the Christian exclusivist. There are two moves in
the Free Will Defense: (I) to deny that the objector has shown
(1) and the evil in question to be broadly logically inconsistent,
and (II) to suggest a possibly true proposition that together
with (1) entails the existence of the particular evil, thereby
showing the co-existence of God and that evil to be broadly logically
possible. The Theodicist will go on to argue that (III) the proposed
proposition is not merely possible but plausible. By focusing
in his most recent contribution almost exclusively on task (II),
Talbott turns the spotlight away from (I) and from the extraordinarily
difficult task with which he is confronted in meeting conditions
(i), (ii), and (iii) above. Let us in the interest of clarity
therefore address separately the three questions raised by the
Free Will Defense and theodicy.
(I) Has Talbott Shown (1) and (2) to be Inconsistent?
Depending on how the terms in Talbott's premisses are defined,
it is open to the Free Will Defender to point to lacunae at various
places in Talbott's argument. For example, one might deny that
Talbott has shown (P3) to be true, since
God's omnibenevolence does not entail that He intends to do everything
He properly can to promote a person's salvation (even in hell)
if He has already offered that person sufficient grace for salvation
and knows that further efforts would be futile. If Talbott amends
(P3) such that omnibenevolence requires
merely that God always wills the salvation of every person, then
the Free Will Defender may deny that (5) entails a suitably amended
(4), since God's judicial rejection of a person who has freely
spurned His offer of salvation is consistent with God's willing
that that person instead accept His offer. If Talbott should
define "rejection" in such a way that it entails "not
intending the rejected person's salvation," then the Free
Will Defender will deny that (2) entails (5). All of these moves
derive from the Free Will Defender's belief that what Talbott
calls the Rejection Hypothesis is possibly true:
(RH) Some persons will, despite God's best efforts to save
them, freely and irrevocably reject God and thus separate themselves
from God forever.
If Talbott is to carry his argument, he must show that (RH)
is broadly logically impossible.
With that in mind, consider now the opening section to Talbott's
most recent contribution. Here Talbott distinguishes between
broadly logical possibility and merely epistemic possibility,
observing that a proposition's epistemic possibility does not
suffice to establish its broadly logical possibility. He rightly
points out that questions about the latter "are sometimes
exceedingly difficult and, and as a practical matter, impossible
to answer in a definitive way."{6}
Talbott complains that I set out "a bewildering number of
unsupported assertions to the effect that this or that is logically
possible"{7} in
an effort to deduce the possibility of what he calls the "Damnation
Thesis":
(DT) There exists at least one sinner S such that S
will never be reconciled to God and thus never be saved.
He charges that I confuse what it would take to demonstrate
that, for all we know, (DT) is true and what is would
take to demonstrate that (DT) is possible in the broadly logical
sense. Talbott argues that I fail both to establish that
(DT) is broadly logically possible and to undermine Talbott's
argument that (DT) is broadly logically impossible.
The distinction to which Talbott draws our attention, namely,
epistemic versus broadly logical possibility, is an important
one, and one which I failed to delineate clearly in my critique
of Talbott's universalism. Nonetheless, it does seem to me that
Talbott is trying to foist upon me a project which I did not
undertake in that critique, for I neither enunciated (DT) nor
tried to provide a deductive proof of it, as Talbott represents.
Rather my principal strategy was to attack Talbott's demonstration
that (RH) is impossible. He argued that (RH) is not broadly logically
possible because (i) the choice specified in (RH) is incoherent
and (ii) even if such a choice were coherent, necessarily God
would not permit it. I in turn tried to show that his arguments
for (i) and (ii) fail.{8}
My primary purpose was thus not to establish the possibility
of (DT), but to deny that Talbott had shown (RH) to be impossible.
It is important to understand that at this stage of the argument
the Free Will Defender is not obliged even to establish the broadly
logical possibility of (RH); all he has to do is undercut the
universalist's attempts to prove its impossibility. And the crucial
point here is that in order for the Free Will Defender to accomplish
that purely negative and defensive task, the epistemic possibility
of (RH) is sufficient. Thus I am under no obligation to establish
the broadly logical possibility of the Molinist hypotheses I
set forth; all that is required to defeat Talbott's arguments
against (RH) is that some of the "bewildering number"
of suggestions I made be epistemically possible.
I.1. Is the Choice Specified in (RH) Incoherent or even Relevant?
Let us consider Talbott's first argument against (RH), that
the choice involved is incoherent. Here two issues arise.
I.1.i. Has Talbott Proved that Transcircumstantial Damnation
is Incoherent?
The debate here mirrors the seventeenth century Jesuit discussions
concerning whether God has congruent grace for every possible
person, that is, grace that is extrinsically efficacious but
infallible in winning the free consent of the person to whom
it is extended. According to the Congruist, God has congruent
grace for every person He could possibly create. Now Talbott
is a sort of modern day Congruist; nay, more than that, he is
a hyper-Congruist. For he holds not merely that God has congruent
grace for every possible person, but that, necessarily, God extends
such grace to every person He creates, that it is logically impossible
for any person to finally reject God's salvation. Congruism is
a radical and traditionally controversial doctrine; its falsity
certainly seems epistemically possible. But Talbott contends
that hyper-Congruism can be shown to be true. His argument is
that in every possible world God does His best to save every
person and that there can be no motivation for any person to
reject irrevocably God's best efforts to save him. I responded
with two questions: (i) Is it not possible that the motivation
for rejecting God is the will to self-autonomy? (ii) Is it not
possible that rejection of God is due to a perversity which lacks
any further motivation? So long as an affirmative answer to these
questions is even epistemically possible, Talbott has failed
to prove that (RH) is logically impossible and, hence, that (1)
and (2) are inconsistent.
In response to my first suggestion, Talbott emphasizes that
the decision to reject God must be "fully informed,"
which notion Talbott defines as a decision which "does not
rest upon ignorance, or misinformation, or deception of any kind."{9} Given that God wills
for me exactly what I at the most fundamental level will for
myself--supreme happiness--, it follows that anyone in a position
to make a fully informed decision would have the strongest conceivable
motive not to reject God. Talbott's view is that in every possible
world containing persons in need of salvation, God eventually
places every person in circumstances in which he can make a fully
informed decision about salvation and that that decision is always
affirmative.
Persuasive as this argument may appear at first blush, a little
reflection will show, I think, that it is question-begging. For
suppose that the Free Will Defender responds that someone may
be fully informed of God's intentions toward him, but out of
a desire for self-autonomy refuses even supreme happiness because
its price--bowing the knee to God--is too high. Why could not
someone's hatred of God be so implacable that he chooses to reject
God rather than be supremely happy? Talbott responds that such
a case--Milton's Satan being a paradigm example--"hardly
illustrates a fully informed decision to reject God."{10} Such a person still
labors under so many illusions that his decision is less than
fully informed.
This response raises the suspicion that in Talbott's view
any decision to reject God is by definition not "fully informed,"
since a person who rejects God is by the nature of the case deceived
and no "fully informed" decision rests upon "deception
of any kind." We are then surely justified in questioning
whether those who reject God must make "fully informed"
decisions in this idiosyncratic sense. For such persons may be
justifiably regarded as self-deceived, and it may not
be within God's power to destroy such self-deceptions without
destroying such persons' freedom. For self-deception, being rooted
in the free will of the creature, may be as impenetrable to God's
grace as the free will itself. Indeed, in the traditional Christian
doctrine of sin the notion of self-deception lay at the heart
of all man's sinful acts and especially his sinful rejection
of God. God's removal of the deception in some persons could
require abrogation of the freedom of the will itself, the freedom
to deceive oneself. Talbott's argument is therefore either question-begging
(because it rules out a fully informed rejection of God by definition)
or unsound (because nothing requires that sinners' rejection
of God be free of deception of any sort). Because Talbott's argument
is not cogent, it remains epistemically possible that the will
to self-autonomy may motivate rejection of God even under the
best of circumstances.
What then of my second suggestion, the human perversity being
what it is, perhaps no motivation is necessary for the decision
to reject God? Talbott's response is that such an irrational
decision cannot be characterized as free. Only a rational agent
can act freely, so that someone who acts contrary to his own
interest without any motive for doing so is not a rational agent
and so is not capable of performing free actions. Again, however,
this line of argument seems question-begging. We should not think
of a decision sprung from perverseness as like a drug addiction
or a quantum leap, but as something which issues out of one's
own twisted moral character. Persons who just are evil may do
wrong for its own sake and spurn God just to spurn Him. Since
the decision arises from agent causation--albeit an evil, perverse
agent--, I do not see why it cannot be described as free unless
we simply define "free" to exclude such irrational
acts. But if we adopt this idiosyncratic view of freedom, then
why think that sinners must be free in that sense? There is a
strong Christian tradition rooted in the New Testament that sinners
are in fact not free, that they are slaves of sin and self. In
this sense, those who reject God are not truly free. But because
theirs is a self-bondage, rooted in their own will, which is
capable of receiving God's grace, but, perversely, refuses to
do so, they are culpable for that bondage. So, again, if Talbott's
argument is not question-begging, it is still unsound because
nothing has been shown to require that the decision to reject
God be "free" in his peculiar sense. Hence, he has
failed to show (RH) to be logically impossible.
Remarkably, Talbott in the end concedes, "at least for
the sake of argument," that
(A) There exists at least one creaturely essence E such that,
for any circumstances C in which the instantiation of E would
be free in the matter of being reconciled to God, the instantiation
of E would in fact freely refuse to be reconciled to God in C
is possibly true.{11}
If (A) turns out to be true, then there are creaturely essences
which have the property of transcircumstantial damnation, and
not only hyper-Congruism but even ordinary Congruism is false.
Talbott observes that (A), however, does not entail (DT), since
God need not instantiate any of these creaturely essences. But
here Talbott is shifting the burden of proof. For no one has
claimed that (A) entails (DT). What is claimed is that no cogent
argument has been given to show that (RH) is logically impossible.
By conceding the possibility of (A), Talbott gives up one of
his principal arguments against (RH), namely, that the choice
specified in (RH) is incoherent.{12}
That means that he shall have to rely on other arguments to prove
the logical impossibility of (RH).
I.1.ii. Has Talbott Proved that (RH) Entails Transcircumstantial
Damnation?
In my critique of Talbott's universalism, I made a sort of
concession of my own, namely, I pointed out that even if Congruism
were true, so that for any creaturely essence E there is a set
of circumstances in which God can win the free, affirmative response
of the instantiation of E to His salvific grace, (RH) is still
epistemically possible because (RH) does not entail that (A)
is true. I pointed out that even if for every created person
S, there is a set of circumstances C in which S
affirmatively responds to God's grace and is saved, it does not
follow that there is a compossible set of circumstances in which
all created persons freely embrace salvation. More than that,
even if S1 would in C1 freely accept salvation and S2 would in C2 freely accept salvation and C1 and C2 are
compossible, to claim that in C1
& C2, S1
would freely accept salvation or that in C1
& C2, S2
would freely accept salvation would be to commit the counterfactual
fallacy of strengthening the antecedent. Thus the Free Will Defender
could embrace Congruism, but maintain that it is (epistemically)
possible that there are no feasible worlds in which all free
persons accept salvation.
Talbott counters that without transcircumstantial damnation
it is logically impossible that all feasible worlds should be
such that in each of them some person rejects salvation. There
is no feasible world in which every person freely accepts salvation
only if every creaturely essence suffers from transcircumstantial
damnation. So long as some essences lack this property, there
is a world feasible to God in which all persons are freely saved.
Talbott thus regards
B. There are feasible worlds in which some persons are freely
reconciled to God; but for any feasible world W, if in
W some persons are freely reconciled to God, then
in W some persons irrevocably reject God
as "quite impossible".{13}
In opposition to (B) Talbott proclaims his "Glorious
Feasibility Thesis"
(GFT) Necessarily, for any collection C of persons who do
not suffer from transworld reprobation, there is a feasible world
in which every member of C is freely reconciled to God.
In defense of (GFT), he argues, "For any two persons,
S and S, if there is a feasible set of circumstances in
which S is freely reconciled to God and there is a feasible
set of circumstances in which S' is freely reconciled to God,
then there is also a feasible set of circumstances in which S
and S' are both freely reconciled to God."{14}
Notice, however, that even if sound, this argument does not
establish (GFT); a "feasible set of circumstances"
is not synonymous with a "feasible world," the latter
differing from the former in maximality. The Free Will Defender
could admit that there are circumstances in which S and
S' are both freely reconciled to God without conceding
that there is a feasible world in which all persons are freely
reconciled to God.{15}
But is Talbott's argument in any case sound? In support of
it, he explains that in C1, S
would encounter a set of appearances such that, if God were to
provide him with just those appearances, S would freely be reconciled
to God; similarly in C2, S'
would encounter a set of appearances such that, if God would
provide him with just those appearances, S' would freely be reconciled
to God. These two sets of appearances need not cohere with each
other, and God can vary how things appear to S' without
varying how things appear to S. So even if C1 and C2 are
logically inconsistent, there would still be a feasible set of
circumstances C3 consisting of
God's providing S and S' respectively with the
appearances conducive to their each being freely reconciled to
God.
Talbott recognizes that this account might require God to
engage in deception. Indeed, it might involve deception on a
massive scale, with each person hermetically sealed in his own
illusory world. Talbott contemplates "spiritual realms which
have no ordinary physical connection with our universe"--assuming,
indeed, that there exists such a common universe--and which are
tailor-made, complete with "misleading appearances concerning
the existence or the fate of other persons," for winning
the free, affirmative response of its real, non-illusory denizen(s)
to God's grace.{16}
Talbott envisions for each person, if need be, "a billion
lifetimes, a billion different realms and universes and sets
of appearances, a billion ways (including a billion different
forms of deception)" to secure a person's salvation.{17}
He admits that this defense of (GFT) might lead one to question
whether God could engage in such deception and whether, therefore,
C3 is really possible. In defense
of the possibility of the envisioned scenario, Talbott offers
the justification that God would have a morally sufficient reason
for deceiving people (presumably, their salvation) and that such
deception is merely temporary.
A number of things can be said in response to this argument.
First, I think we must say at the very least that we have no
firm moral intuitions for thinking a world involving states of
affairs like C3 to be broadly logically
possible. But without such a basis, we have no good grounds for
thinking (RH) to be impossible. For my part, worlds based on
systematic deception by God of human persons seem morally unconscionable
and therefore impossible. As worthy an end as universal salvation
is, God could not utilize immoral means for achieving such an
end. And in deceiving human persons in the way Talbott envisions,
God would be violating their personhood and so acting immorally.
For God would be placing persons in situations in which, for
example, their spouses, children, and friends, with whom they
enter into supposedly meaningful and intimate relationships,
turn out to be mere illusions. One's life struggles, the expressions
of tenderness, the confessions of fears to a trusted companion,
the sacrifices for persons one loved, one's apologies and extensions
of forgiveness, the myriad emotions of sympathy, anger, shame,
bitterness, compassion--all were an interaction with illusion,
a world of maya. This constitutes a profound violation
of human dignity. Talbott criticizes one of my proposals because
God, in expunging from a person's memory the knowledge of lost
family members, would not be providing that person with a supremely
worthwhile happiness: "No loving father, for example--not
even one whose daughter endures a brutal rape and murder and
not even one whose son commits suicide--would want to remain
blissfully ignorant about what happened . . . . and the idea
that he might want to have all memory of a son or daughter obliterated
from his mind--that he might prefer this over his anguish--is
simply preposterous."{18}
But consider: on Talbott's view, a loving father may find out
that in fact he had no son or daughter at all, that he was in
love with a chimaera; his family has been truly lost to him,
for in fact he has no family--only the delusions caused by God.
Such a one has been violated in the deepest core of his person
by being thus deceived. Indeed, one is compelled to wonder whether
such persons, when confronted by God with the truth about their
illusory pasts, will continue to accept the salvation won by
their delusion--which makes the difference between feasible circumstances
and feasible worlds acute for Talbott's case. Talbott might say
that so great a deception would not be required by God to bring
all created persons to salvation--but then how do we know? Is
it not epistemically possible that in order to achieve a significant
number of saved without any lost, the deception would have to
be that great, at least for one person? To even so deceive one
person would implicate God in sin, and so any such world would
be impossible. I find it a telling weakness of the responses
to my Molinist perspective on Christian exclusivism that in the
end they inevitably have recourse to systematic deception on
God's part{19}--an
expedient which is at the very least dubious and consequently
no proof in any sense of the impossibility of (RH).
Second, even if there are feasible worlds involving states
of affairs like C3, so that (GFT)
is true, that fact does not imply the impossibility of (RH).
For even if some such world is feasible for God, God may prefer
not to create such a world based on deception, but to create
instead a world in which people find themselves in real circumstances
and are offered by God sufficient grace for salvation, people
whose choices are respected by God. In order to provide grounds
for thinking (RH) to be impossible, Talbott must show that God
is morally obligated to choose C3-worlds
rather than non-deceptive worlds. Again, we have no firm basis
for thinking that God is so obligated. As I pointed out in my
original article, C3-worlds could
involve drawbacks that would influence God not to prefer them
over non-deceptive worlds, even though in the latter some people
freely reject His salvation. So long as it is (epistemically)
possible that God prefer a straightforward world in which not
all are saved over a deceptive world in which all are saved through
delusion, then (RH) is also (epistemically) possible.
Third, it is not evident that Talbott has succeeded in averting
logical invalidity in his argument. In order to avoid the fallacy
of strengthening the antecedent, Talbott argues that if in C1 S would be freely saved and in C2 S' would be freely saved, then in
C3 S and S' would
both be freely saved. Let, then, Cn
= "Circumstances n obtain," Sn
= "Sn will freely accept salvation,"
and ACn = "The appearance
of Cn obtains." In order to
avoid the fallacy of strengthening the antecedent, Talbott infers
from
6. C1 S1
7. C2 S2,
that
8. C3 S1 ·
S2.
He justifies this inference by supposing that
9. (AC1 ·
AC2) = C3.
We thus infer (8) from
10. (AC1 ·
AC2) S1 ·
S2.
But how do we know that (10) is true? The answer is that to S1, C1 and AC1
are indistinguishable; similarly for S2
and C2 and AC2. So we may affirm
11. (C1 S1) É
(AC1 S1),
12. (C2 S2) É
(AC2 S2).
From (6), (11) and (7), (12), it follows that
13.(AC1 S1),
14.(AC2 S2).
But how do we move from (13), (14), to (10)? The answer seems
to be: by strengthening the antecedent of (13) or (14), which
is logically invalid. Hence, the argument for (8) is unsound.
It seems to me, then, that even if we were to concede Congruism,
Talbott still has not shown (RH) to be logically impossible,
since his refutation of the hypothesis that worlds in which all
persons freely accept salvation are infeasible for God involves
the dubious claim that God might deceive people in order to win
their salvation, fails to show that God is morally obligated
to prefer a deceptive world to a straightforward one in which
not all are saved, and seems to be logically invalid.
It seems to me, therefore, that we can conclude that Talbott's
first argument for the logical impossibility of (RH) fails, for
he has not shown either that the choice allegedly envisioned
in (RH) is logically incoherent nor that such a choice is required
if all feasible worlds are to be such that in none of them are
all free persons saved. I think we can safely conclude that Talbott
has not met so far condition (iii) of a successful presentation
of the soteriological problem of evil, not to mention conditions
(i) and (ii).
I. 2. Could God Create Worlds in which Not All Persons are
Saved?
It will be recalled that Talbott had a second major argument
against (RH), namely, that even if there are no feasible worlds
in which all persons are freely saved, necessarily God would
not create a world in which some persons are damned.{20} Rather, if He created at all, He would
create a world in which free will is sacrificed to achieve universal
salvation. Talbott's argument for this contention was a curious
one to the effect that God must choose a world in which all are
saved because otherwise, the supreme happiness of the blessed
would be undermined by their knowledge of the existence of the
damned. It seemed to me that this problem could be averted by
denying that the blessed have any such knowledge. It seems possible,
for example, that God could expunge from their minds any knowledge
of the damned or, better, that the overwhelming presence of Christ
would drive from the minds of the blessed the consciousness of
the damned. Again, the Free Will Defender need not prove that
these hypotheses are any more than epistemically possible, but
Talbott, if he is to defeat (RH), must prove them broadly logically
impossible.
Talbott argues that my hypotheses are broadly logically impossible
because in neither case would the blessed enjoy "supremely
worthwhile happiness," which is essential to salvation.
Supremely worthwhile happiness is, first, "the kind of happiness
that could survive a complete disclosure of truth about the universe;
and second, it is the kind that one possesses only when one is
filled with love for others."{21}
Before we look at Talbott's detailed argumentation, we should
do well to reflect for a moment on this peculiar sort of happiness.
I think it does make sense to speak of different degrees of worth
of happiness. For example, the happiness of the sadist is not
as worthwhile as the happiness of the care-giver. Here the worth
of the happiness is related to the moral value of the action
which gives rise to it. But it seems to me dubious and even false
that supremely worthwhile happiness entails the ability to survive
a full disclosure of the truth. For a happiness which would, ceteris paribus, be diminished by the
disclosure of a tragic truth about a loved one seems more worthwhile
than one which would survive undiminished. Indeed,
on Talbott's own reasoning the happiness of a person who is filled
with love for others must be diminished on learning the truth
of a loved one's misfortune; otherwise, we could maintain that
the blessed do love the damned, but that their happiness remains
nonetheless undiminished by the knowledge of their terrible estate.
Thus, supremely worthwhile happiness does not entail the ability
to survive a full disclosure of the truth; if the truth is tragic,
quite the opposite is the case.
The problem is that Talbott has conflated supreme happiness
with supremely worthwhile happiness. A happiness which is supremely
worthwhile need not, indeed, in some cases, cannot be supreme
happiness, that is, happiness untinged by sadness. Aware of the
fate of the lost, the blessed in heaven could have supremely
worthwhile happiness without being supremely happy.
Talbott would perhaps contend that salvation entails supreme
happiness which is supremely worthwhile. If the happiness of
the blessed is to be both, then there must be no damned; otherwise,
if the truth of their existence were disclosed, the supreme happiness
of the blessed, precisely because it is supremely worthwhile,
would be undermined. But such reasoning would be modally fallacious.
The blessed's happiness being both supreme and supremely worthwhile
does not entail being able to survive complete disclosure of
the truth. If the blessed are unaware that the damned exist,
their happiness can be supreme, but it can also be supremely
worth-while because it would be diminished if this truth
were known.
In order to make his argument stick, Talbott must maintain
that happiness which is both supreme and supremely worthwhile
entails one's being conscious of the full truth and yet one's
happiness remaining undiminished by it. But I do not see any
basis to think the happiness of a person who has a complete knowledge
of the truth is any more worthwhile for that reason than that
of a person who lacks such knowledge. If my son is listed MIA
in Vietnam would my happiness be made more worthwhile by the
discovery that he was executed by the North Vietnamese? No doubt,
as Talbott says, I would want to know that painful truth and
in a sense would even welcome it, despite the pain it would bring.
But that does not entail that such knowledge makes my happiness
more worthwhile than it would have been without it. The mere
possession of more information seems irrelevant to the worth
of one's happiness. What is relevant is how one's happiness would
be affected by the disclosure of such painful knowledge. Happiness
which, ceteris paribus, increases with news of a loved
one's good fortune or decreases with the news of his misfortune
is more worthwhile than a happiness which survives indifferent
the disclosure of such information. But the mere lack or possession
of information does not decrease or increase the worthwhileness
of the happiness one experiences. Thus I do not see why supremely
worthwhile happiness entails complete knowledge of the truth.
Unaware of the existence of the lost, the happiness of the saved
in heaven, could be both supreme (because it is untinged by sadness)
and supremely worthwhile (because it would be diminished were
they aware of the fate of the lost).
Talbott therefore needs to prove that it is logically impossible
that the blessed should be unaware of the existence of the damned.
Consider then my first hypothesis, that God removes or withholds
from the blessed any knowledge of the existence of the damned.
Talbott agrees that it is sometimes right to withhold painful
information from someone, but he insists that this is always
a concession to that person's poor health or psychological/spiritual
immaturity. Since the blessed are presumably not characterized
by such conditions, it would be immoral of God to withhold from
them knowledge of the damned. Moreover, Talbott argues, the deception
contemplated in the present hypothesis is immoral because it
is an eternal, not merely temporary, deception.
To deal with Talbott's second point first, I think we are
justified in resisting his characterization of the hypothesis
as "deception." It would
be deceptive of God to make the blessed believe that the lost
were saved when in fact they are not. But that is not the proposal.
God's merely erasing any memory of the lost does not involve
God's deceiving the blessed about the state of the lost. The
blessed entertain no false beliefs about the lost; they simply
have no beliefs about them at all. The doctrine of progressive
revelation teaches us that while God is morally bound to reveal
to us nothing but the truth, He is not bound to reveal to us
the whole truth or, for that matter, even the truth about some
thing. Hence, I do not see that Talbott has proven that God's
removing or withholding knowledge of the lost from the minds
of the blessed in order to secure their supreme happiness is
either deceptive or immoral.
As for Talbott's first point, it seems to me very mootable
that appropriate withholding of needless, painful information
is in every case a concession to poor health and immaturity.
Is it due to poor health or immaturity that we hold closed coffin
funerals, for example? Or why we do not convey to a friend a
secret insult uttered by someone in the past? Or why we do not
ask forgiveness of someone for having once despised him because
we thought him ugly? It seems to me that there are plenty of
occasions on which we withhold information from healthy, mature
people simply because we love them and know that the disclosure
of such information would do absolutely no good, but only hurt
them. In any case, I fail to see why God is morally obligated
to permit the saved to have knowledge of the damned.
What then of the second hypothesis, that the blessed know
of the state of the lost, but are not conscious of it because
of the overwhelming joy inspired by Christ's presence? Talbott
rejoins that if the beatific vision drives from the mind of the
blessed the consciousness of the lost, then those experiencing
such a vision become less loving (presumably because they no
longer love the lost). The beatific vision would "make the
redeemed less loving and thus more calloused," which is
incompatible with supremely worthwhile happiness.{22}
This objection seems a clear non
sequitur. A person is less loving and more callous only if
he fails to love all those persons of whom he is aware; but it
would be fatuous to so describe someone for failing to love a
person of whose existence he is completely unaware. Supremely
worthwhile happiness only entails loving unconditionally every
person of whom one is aware and is therefore compatible with
the hypothesis in question.
Up to this point I have argued that Talbott has not shown
that it is logically impossible for the damned to exist and the
blessed to experience supreme happiness which is supremely worthwhile.
But suppose I am wrong about this. It still does not follow that
(RH) is false. For if, given certain counterfactuals of freedom,
it is not feasible for God to actualize a world in which the
blessed, despite the existence of the damned, experience supreme
happiness which is supremely worthwhile, it does not follow that
universalism is true. For happiness that is achieved at the expense
of abrogating the free will of creatures is not supremely worthwhile
either. Indeed, it seems to be plausible that this forced happiness
is less worthwhile that the happiness achieved by the blessed's
lack of awareness of the damned. So God may not be able to actualize
in the blessed both supreme happiness and supremely worthwhile
happiness. Perhaps Talbott would say that God would therefore
be morally obligated to refrain from the creation of persons
altogether. But I think such a response is obviously false: if
God can achieve supreme happiness in the blessed, even if that
happiness is not supremely worthwhile, His creating that
enormously worthwhile supreme happiness is a lot better than
creating no happiness at all! Hence, Talbott has not proved that
it is logically impossible for God to bestow on the blessed a
supreme happiness which involves their unawareness of the damned.
It seems to me, therefore, that Talbott has failed to show
that it is logically necessary that God refrain from creating
a world in which some persons freely reject His saving grace.
It is epistemically possible that God erase from the minds of
the redeemed any knowledge of the lost or that the presence of
Christ and the happiness he brings should drive such knowledge
from their consciousness. Therefore, Talbott's second argument
for the logical impossibility of (RH) fails.
In summary, neither of Talbott's two arguments succeeds in
showing (RH) to be broadly logically impossible. Therefore, no
inconsistency has been shown to exist between (1) and (2).
(II) Can (1) and (2) Be Shown to be Consistent?
In any original piece, I asserted that the Free Will Defender
can not only rebut attempts such as Talbott's to prove that (1)
and (2) are broadly logically inconsistent, but that he can prove
them to be consistent by specifying a proposition which is consistent
with (1) and entails (2). Unfortunately, as Talbott emphasizes,
the difficulty with this approach is that the universalist who
denies the possibility of (2) will inevitably also deny the possibility
of the new, proposed proposition. In the face of such modal scepticism,
I must confess that I do not know how to construct a proof that
(1) and (2) are consistent in the broadly logical sense.
Perhaps the best that the Free Will Defender can do at this
point is to emphasize how modest his claim is, to hope that his
proposed third proposition both is more perspicuously consistent
with (1) than is (2) and is explanatorily superior to the bald
assertion of (2), so that the consistency of (2) with (1) becomes
more evident, and to refute any attempts to cast doubt on the
possibility of the new, proposed proposition.
Consider, then, the proposition
C. Since there is no world (without over-riding deficiencies)
feasible for God in which all persons are freely saved, God has
chosen a world having an optimal balance between those who freely
accept His grace for salvation and those who freely reject His
grace for salvation.
The Free Will Defender is not claiming that (C) is true. In
the actual world, there may be suitable feasible
worlds in which all persons are freely saved; indeed, maybe the
actual world is one of these and universalism is correct! Whatever
true counterfactuals of creaturely freedom confront God in the
actual world, in other possible worlds different sets of such
counterfactuals (or world-types for God{23}) obtain. The claim of the Free Will Defender
is that in at least one possible world W the world-type
which confronts God logically prior to His creative decree in
W is such that in no suitable feasible world is every
free creature saved. The modesty of this claim is evident from
the fact that the Free Will Defender can also freely grant the
possibility of the claim
D. In every world of free creatures feasible for God, God
wins the free, affirmative response to His saving grace on the
part of every person.
That is to say, in at least one possible world W* the
world-type confronting God in W* is such that in every
world of free creatures feasible for Him all persons are freely
saved. One can also admit the possibility of the opposite claim
E. In every world of free creatures feasible for God, no persons
freely accept His saving grace.
That is to say, in at least one possible world W' the
world-type confronting God in W' is such that in every
world of free creatures feasible for Him He is unable to win
a free response to His saving grace on the part of anyone (a
hyper-Calvinist might hold the actual world to be such a world).
The possibilities are endless. To assert that in some possible
world or other God is confronted with a range of feasible worlds
which does not include a suitable world in which everyone is
freely saved is modest, indeed.
Moreover, (C) seems to be more perspicuously consistent with
(1) than does (2). (C) seems consistent with God's omnipotence,
since counterfactuals of creaturely freedom are outside of God's
control and yet place no non-logical limit on His omnipotence.{24} It also seems consistent
with God's omniscience, since God's decree to create a particular
world is based on His middle knowledge, which includes knowledge
of all counterfactuals of creaturely freedom. Finally, the claim
seems consistent with His omnibenevolence, since God is said
to choose the world with the optimal balance of saved and unsaved
and to accord sufficient grace for salvation even to the unsaved,
who He knew would reject Him. Furthermore, (1) makes the possibility
of (2) more evident by giving some explanation of how a state
of affairs like that described in (2) could obtain. We see that
(2) could obtain when there is no suitable world available to
God in which all persons are freely saved. What would damn people
would be their own free rejection of God's saving grace. Despite
this unhappy situation, God, possessing middle knowledge and
omnibenevolence, could still be counted on to pick a world with
an optimal balance of saved and unsaved. Thus, (C) helps to make
(2) more evidently possible by making sense of how (2) is consistent
with (1).
Consider now, by contrast, Talbott's position. Talbott is
not asserting merely that in the actual world, all persons are
saved, nor is he even asserting merely (D), that in every world
feasible for God all persons are saved. He is not even claiming
merely that in every possible world, every world feasible for
God is one in which all persons are saved. Rather he is claiming
that in no possible world whatsoever does a person freely reject
God's offer of salvation. This is a radically immodest claim
in contrast to (C) and is certainly in need of justification.
Of course, Talbott need not establish so radical a claim in
order to neutralize this step in the Free Will Defense. He need
do no more than give some reason why we should not think (C)
to be logically possible. Here Talbott's arguments against the
broadly logical possibility of (A) become relevant. He argues
first, as we have seen, that there is no reason to think that
it is possible that a person would make a fully informed and
free decision to reject God, and, second, that there is no reason
to think that it is possible that a fully-informed decision to
accept God would not be free.
We have already looked at the first of these allegations,
and what I suggested there certainly seems logically possible:
that in some world or other the creaturely will to self-autonomy
and the bent to self-deception is so strong that some persons
irrevocably resist God; or again, that in some possible world
people are so evil that they reject God for its own sake. Even
if these are not the case in the actual world, are they not at
least possible?
The only way in which God could save such people would be
by a freedom-removing revelation of Himself. That brings us to
Talbott's second point: he thinks the notion of a freedom-removing
revelation is incoherent. He writes, "I fail to see how
a knowledge of the truth, even where it renders certain actions
psychologically impossible, in any way restricts one's freedom
to perform such actions--as if those in possession of the beatific
vision are no longer free agents."{25} Talbott's claim is problematic. The revelation
of which we speak is less like the communication of knowledge
than the presentation of an irresistible lure that overpowers
the will. The notion of "psychological impossibility"
needs clarification; in the case in which sinners are drawn irresistibly
to God as iron filings to a magnet, it does seem to be freedom-removing.
Indeed, I do not find it objectionable to affirm that the blessed
in heaven in the presence of Christ no longer have the freedom
to reject him, since the epistemic distance necessary for such
freedom has been removed.
In the end Talbott admits that this is a "difficult and
controversial" matter and is willing to concede that (A)
is logically possible. But he is still not prepared to concede
the logical possibility of (C). Talbott argues that we have no
reason to suppose that it is possible that God values the free
will of His creatures above their salvation. "If a knowledge
of the truth, the ability to see things as they are, is incompatible
with free agency, as some conceive of it, then so much the worse
for the free agency so conceived," declares Talbott. ".
. . we have no reason to believe it even possible that God would
withhold a revelation of truth from some persons, or keep them
in perpetual bondage to ignorance and illusion, merely to maintain
forever the artificial kind of free agency that Craig imagines."{26}
This consideration has, I think, a strong emotional appeal.
Those of us who have unbelieving family and friends no doubt
often feel that if they will not freely give their lives to Christ,
it would be worth it if God would simply overpower their wills
and save them in spite of themselves; do doubt, too, we feel
that if we had not freely yielded our lives to God, then we wish
that God would have overpowered our wills and saved us anyway.
But as strong as such feelings are, they do not change the fact
that such an action on God's part amounts to salvation by divine
rape. For God to subvert the will of someone who chooses to reject
His grace would be to violate their personhood, and that God
necessarily will not do. More than our own, God's heart also
breaks for those of our family and friends who reject His love
and salvation, but God will not force them to repent. Hence,
I regard Talbott's conjecture as logically impossible; at the
very least we must say that in some possible world in which God
faces such a situation He chooses not to overpower sinners' wills,
and that is all the Free Will Defense needs.
We come now to Talbott's attacks on the possibility of (B),
which also have relevance to the possibility of (C). His opening
move is to enunciate a proposition as equally plausible as (B)
and yet incompatible with it, thereby removing any grounds for
our thinking (B) to be logically possible. Suppose, says Talbott,
we say that God's victory over sin is complete iff God manages
to repair all of the damage that sinners do (both to themselves
and others). In accord with this notion, Talbott proclaims the
"Victorious God Thesis:"
(VGT) Necessarily, God would have created persons whom He
knew would sin only if He also knew that He could achieve a complete
victory over sin.
If all feasible worlds in which persons sin are worlds in
which not all are freely saved, then (VGT) entails that either
God desists from creating worlds in which He knew people would
sin or else He removes their freedom with respect to salvation
to the extent necessary to ensure universal salvation.
Once again, however, Talbott's argument seems question-begging,
based on an idiosyncratic definition of terms. As Christian thinkers
we certainly affirm that God shall have a complete victory over
sin, and we will probably concur that God would not have created
a sinful world unless He knew His victory over sin would be complete.
But the notion of a complete victory over sin according to the
New Testament is that every wrong ever committed is either efficaciously
expiated by the blood of Christ or punished with its just dessert.
In the end injustice will not prevail; the scales of God's justice
will be balanced. Just as heaven is the triumph of God's grace
and love, so hell is the triumph of His holiness and justice.
God's complete victory over sin does not entail that He repair
the damage sinners do to themselves; on the contrary it entails
that unexpiated sin receive its just recompense in the sinner.
Since Talbott's definition of "complete victory over sin"
is not that of the New Testament, and Talbott gives no philosophical
argument in support of (VGT), the Christian thinker ought to
reject (VGT) as Talbott understands it. Thus, the mere enunciation
of (VGT) does nothing to undermine the logical possibility of
(B) or (C).
As for Talbott's attempt to oppose (GFT) to (B) or (C), I
have already commented on what seems to me the logical impossibility
of so profound and massive a divine deception.
Finally, as we have seen, Talbott tries to undermine (C) by
trying to show that it is incompatible with the supremely worthwhile
happiness of the blessed, which attempt, I have argued, is a
singular failure.
So in answer to the question of this section, we must admit
that we have no proof of the consistency of (C) with (1) and
therefore of the consistency of (2) with (1). But (C) does seem prima facie to be consistent with (1)
and can help us to see how (2) can also be consistent with (1).
Moreover, no good reason exists to reject the logical possibility
of (C). Modal scepticism is in any case a two-edged sword: to
the extent that it undermines our confidence of the logical possibility
of (C) it also makes Talbott's attempt to prove that (1) and
(2) are not true in any possible world a virtual impossibility.
III. Are (1) and (2) Plausibly True?
We come at last to the Theodicist's question concerning, not
what is true in some possible world, but what is true in the
actual world. I suggested that not only are (1) and (C) possibly
true, but they may very well be in fact true and therefore (2)
true as well. Notice that like the case of the Free Will Defender,
the Theodicist's case involves a negative and a positive aspect:
he asserts first, that his interlocutor has not shown the co-existence
of God and the evil in question to be implausible and, second,
that their co-existence is plausible. In order to undercut his
opponent's argument, he need only succeed in the first, defensive
move; success in the second move would be the
coup de grâce. Notice, too, that the Theodicist
also makes a modest claim: he does not assert that (C), for example,
is true or can be proved to be true, but merely that it may well
be true. The Theodicist does not claim to know the actual reason
why the evil in question exists, but he offers suggestions which
are not mere possibilities, but plausible explanations.
In confronting the soteriological problem of evil, the Theodicist
can make the same moves that Plantinga makes concerning the probabilistic
problem of evil, such as noting the fogginess of the notion of
probability, the relativity of probabilities to background information,
and so forth.{27} But I should like to confront the problem
more directly; namely, I do not think that Talbott has shown
(C) to be implausible at all--indeed, I think this proposition
could very well be true.
What is implausible about (C)? Consider its assertion that
in no world (without overriding deficiencies) feasible for God
do all people freely accept His salvation. Even if we conceded
that Congruism were true, that would not undercut the plausibility
of (C), since it may well be the case that the con-creation of
all the optimally conducive circumstances for salvation for all
persons is not feasible for God. I think we must say that Talbott's
objection to this thesis, which appeals to God's deceiving people
into salvation, is, if not invalid, very implausible. Given that
God must work with feasible worlds which are less than ideal,
it seems not at all implausible that some people in every world
which is significantly populated would reject Him, despite their
being accorded sufficient grace for salvation.
On behalf of the plausibility of this aspect of (C), certain
background doctrines revealed in Scripture can be adduced. On
the Christian world view, man is regarded as significantly free
vis à vis God.{28}
He is able to rebel against God and is held accountable for it.
Man in his fallen state is, as Luther put it, bent in upon himself,
and this will to self-autonomy is so strong that man would rather
plunge into self-destruction than bend the knee to God. We learn
from Scripture that sin has a hardening effect upon man's heart:
the longer and more determinedly he resists God's grace and the
drawing of the Holy Spirit, the more likely he is to continue
in such a state of rebellion against God (Heb. 3.7-13; cf. Ex.
7-9, Rev. 16.9, 11, 21; 22.11). In my critique of Talbott's views,
I charged that he lacked a serious doctrine of sin, and I reiterate
that charge here. Contrary to Talbott, the New Testament picture
of sin is that those who choose it in opposition to God go from
bad to worse. A biblical doctrine of sin therefore lends credibility
to the possibility that some persons can freely reject God forever.
So do the New Testament warnings against apostasy, which indicate
that a person who has received salvific grace can reject it and
that if he does so, he will be irretrievably lost (Heb. 6.4-8;
10.26-31). If a person who has known God's salvation can irrevocably
reject it, a fortiori so can a
person who has never known it irrevocably reject God's gracious
initiatives for salvation. I have already rejected as impossible
the idea that God might deceive or "jump start" sinners
repeatedly in order to win their acceptance of salvation, since
so to act would not treat their personhood with the respect it
deserves. Moreover, it seems quite plausible, in view of the
mind-boggling complexity of providentially ordering a world of
free creatures, that if there are feasible worlds in which all
persons freely accept God's saving grace then such worlds are
deficient in other respects (for example, by having only a few
persons in them). When one contemplates the incalculable difficulty
of getting a significant number of free creatures to give themselves
freely to God and without deception, then it seems quite plausible
that in any world feasible for God involving a large number of
free persons, some persons would choose to reject Him.
Consider, then, (C)'s second affirmation, that God has chosen
a world with an optimal balance between those who freely accept
and those who freely reject salvation. Given His omnibenevolence,
it seems that God, in the moment logically prior to His creative
decree, would choose a world from among those feasible worlds
having such a balance.{29} Therefore, the actual world is such a world.
Talbott, of course, argues that there are no feasible worlds
in which persons are allowed to reject God. But his argument
on this score, based on the supremely worthwhile happiness of
the saved, is not very compelling. Even if the first option I
suggested strikes one as implausible, the second, based on the
overwhelming joy inspired by Christ's presence, seems to me very
plausible. The Scriptural descriptions of theophanies and epiphanies
(Ex. 33.17-23; Rev. 1.12-17; 21.3-4), as well as the mystical
experiences of Christians down through church history, make it
entirely believable that the presence of God should drive from
consciousness an awareness of the state of the damned. Nor has
Talbott given us any good reason to question the worthwhileness
of this divinely inspired happiness or to think that it is less
worthwhile than a happiness achieved by the abrogation of creaturely
freedom.
In sum, once Talbott's arguments against the logical possibility
of (C) are seen to be unsound, not much remains of them to render
(C) implausible though possible. On the contrary, background
considerations from a biblical world view make it altogether
believable that although God is desirous of saving all human
persons, God was limited in His choice of worlds to those in
which universal salvation did not obtain and that He accordingly
created a world in which the balance between saved and lost is
as favorable as He could achieve.
Conclusion
Once the differing projects of defense and theodicy are properly
delineated, it can be seen that Talbott's endeavor to prove the
logical impossibility of Christian particularism does not succeed.
While he is correct that a positive demonstration of the consistency
of (1) and (2) by the Free Will Defender has not been forthcoming,
the mere epistemic possibility of (RH) undercuts Talbott's own
claim that they are inconsistent. Neither of Talbott's major
thrusts to demonstrate the broadly logical and, hence, epistemic
impossibility of (RH) can be deemed successful. Moreover, the
Molinist Free Will Defender's (C) appears prima
facie to be consistent with (1) and entails (2), and Talbott's
attempts to show its broadly logical impossibility are no more
successful than his objections to (RH). Finally, the Theodicist
seems justified in regarding (C) as a plausible explanation of
how it is that universalism does not obtain in the actual world.
Endnotes
{1}William
Lane Craig, "'No Other Name': a Middle Knowledge Perspective
on the Exclusivity of Salvation through Christ," Faith
and Philosophy 6 (1989): 172-188.
{2}Ibid., p. 180.
{3}Thomas Talbott,
"The Doctrine of Everlasting Punishment," Faith
and Philosophy 7 (1990): 19-42; idem, "Providence, Freedom,
and Human Destiny," Religious Studies 26 (1990):
227-245.
{4}William Lane Craig,
"Talbott's Universalism," Religious Studies
27 (1991): 297-308.
{5}Thomas Talbott,
"Craig on the Possibility of Eternal Damnation," Religious
Studies 28 (1992): 495-510.
{6}Ibid., p. 497.
{7}Ibid.
{8}With respect to
(i) see my summation on p. 304 of Craig, "Talbott's Universalism";
with respect to (ii) see my prospective statement on p. 306.
{9}Talbott, "Eternal
Damnation," p. 500.
{10}Ibid.
{11}Talbott's admission
of the possibility of (A) is problematic in an interesting way.
He cannot consistently affirm that (A) is possible in the broadly
logical sense because he also holds that it is broadly logically
impossible that God permit any person to irrevocably refuse to
be reconciled with God, so that (A) involves what Thomas Flint
calls a "collapsing counterfactual," i.e., a
counterfactual which entails that its antecedent is false (Thomas
P. Flint, "Middle Knowledge and the Doctrine of Infallibility,"
in Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 5: Philosophy of
Religion, ed. James Tomberlin [Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeway
Publishing, 199], pp. 373-393). For if in no world does God permit
persons to refuse reconciliation with Him, then necessarily if
it is true that the instantiation of E were to refuse reconciliation
under any freedom permitting circumstances he were in, then God
does not instantiate E in such circumstances. A collapsing counterfactual
cannot be true, and so Talbott cannot consistently admit the
logical possibility of (A). If he does admit it, then he must
reject his claim that necessarily God does not permit persons
to refuse reconciliation with God. If Talbott holds (A) to be
merely epistemically possible, then he is admitting that for
all we know (A) is in fact true. Such an admission nullifies
his first argument against (RH).
Talbott cannot adopt Flint's solution of asserting that the
counterfactual only counterfactually implies the falsity of its
antecedent, but does not entail it, for then there are possible
worlds in which God permits people to refuse reconciliation with
God. Nor can Talbott adopt Flint's second solution of replacing
(A) with something like
(A') There exists at least one creaturely essence E such that,
for any circumstances C in which the instantiation of E would
be free in the matter of being reconciled to God, the instantiation
of E would not in fact freely consent to be reconciled to God
in C.
because (A') still involves a collapsing counterfactual. Rather
he must affirm something like
(A") There exists at least one creaturely essence E such
that, for any circumstances C, if the instantiation of E were
to be created in C, the instantiation of E would not freely consent
to be reconciled to God.
(A") does not imply that E's instantiation would be damned,
but that, on Talbott's view, he would be saved without his free
consent in some C. Such a position still gives away Talbott's
first argument against the coherence of a choice to reject God.
{12}Perhaps Talbott
would say that he concedes the possibility of (A) only under
an artificial and false conception of "freedom," according
to which a stunning revelation might be freedom-removing. But
under a correct understanding of freedom, (A), or better, (A")
is false. According to this interpretation the instantiation
of E would not freely consent to reconciliation in the artificial
sense, but he would in the correct sense. Such an interpretation
of Talbott's position, however, still undercuts his argument
for the broadly logical impossibility of (RH), since he admits
that his understanding of "freedom" is "a difficult
and controversial-controversial matter" which he does not
try to settle (Talbott, "Eternal Damnation," p. 502).
Therefore, it is epistemically possible that his understanding
of "freedom" is incorrect, thereby undermining his
argument that (RH) is not logically possible.
{13}Talbott, "Eternal
Damnation," p.504.
{14}Ibid., p. 505.
{15}The difference
between the envisioned circumstances C3
and a possible world is evident not only from Talbott's belief
that even God could not create rational agents ex nihilo
with perfect understanding and clarity of vision, but more importantly
from the fact that God's deception, to be moral, must be merely
temporary, so that those who freely accepted salvation
in C3 are freed from their illusions.
This latter circumstance is very important, since it is not at
all evident on Talbott's view that persons who freely accept
salvation in C3 could not, upon
being confronted with the fact of their deception, including
the illusory existence of those they loved, rebel against God
and reject His salvation.
{16}Talbott, "Eternal
Damnation," p. 507.
{17}Ibid.
{18}Ibid., p. 509.
{19}See also David
P. Hunt, "Middle Knowledge and the Soteriological Problem
of Evil," Religious Studies 27 (1991): 3-26, who
envisions the elect interacting with a world populated by soulless
automata.
{20}I have tried
to state this in such a way that it does not involve a collapsing
counterfactual, as does Talbott's statement, "If every creaturely
essence suffered from transworld reprobation and God . . . knew
this, they either He would refuse to instantiate any essences
at all or, if he did instantiate some of them, he would have
a morally sufficient reason not to leave created persons entirely
free with respect to salvation . . ." (Talbott, "Eternal
Damnation," p. 504).
{21}Talbott, "Eternal
Damnation," p. 507.
{22}Ibid., p. 510.
{23}On the notion
of a world-type, see Thomas P. Flint, "The Problem of Divine
Freedom," American Philosophical Quarterly 20 (1983):
255-264.
{24}See Thomas P.
Flint and Alfred J. Freddoso, "Maximal Power," in The
Existence and Nature of God, ed. Alfred J. Freddoso (Notre
Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), pp. 81-113.
{25}Talbott, "Eternal
Damnation," p. 502.
{26}Ibid., pp. 502-503.
{27}Alvin Plantinga,
"The Probabilistic Argument from Evil," Philosophical
Studies 35 (1979): 1-53.
{28}See helpful
discussion in D. A. Carson, Divine Sovereignty and Human Responsibility,
New Foundations Theological Library (Atlanta: John Knox, 1981),
pp. 18-35.
{29}I assume that
an optimal balance exists. If there does not, then God is no
more obliged to create such a balance than He is to create the
"best of all possible worlds."
Copyright (C) William Lane Craig. All Rights Reserved.
Copyright/Reproduction Limitations
This data file/document is the sole property of William
Lane Craig, It may not be altered or edited in any way. It
may be reproduced only in its entirety for circulation as "freeware,"
without charge. All reproductions of this data file and/or document
must contain the copyright notice (i.e., Copyright (c) 1996
William Lane Craig) and this Copyright/Reproduction Limitations
notice.
This data file/document may not be used without the permission
of William Lane Craig for resale or the enhancement of
any other product sold.
William Lane Craig
c/o Leadership University
3440 Sojourn Drive, Suite 200
Carrollton, TX 75006
U. S. A.
Return to the
Protestant Apologetics and Theology page
|