Talbott's Universalism
William Lane Craig
William Lane Craig
is Research Professor of Philosophy at Talbot School of Theology
in La Mirada, California. He lives in Atlanta, Georgia, with
his wife Jan and their two teenage children Charity and John.
At the age of sixteen as a junior in high school, he first heard
the message of the Christian gospel and yielded his life to Christ.
Dr. Craig pursued his undergraduate studies at Wheaton College
(B.A. 1971) and graduate studies at Trinity Evangelical Divinity
School (M.A. 1974; M.A. 1975), the University of Birmingham (England)
(Ph.D. 1977), and the University of Munich (Germany) (D.Theol.
1984). From 1980-86 he taught Philosophy of Religion at Trinity,
during which time he and Jan started their family. In 1987 they
moved to Brussels, Belgium, where Dr. Craig pursued research
at the University of Louvain until 1994.
Thomas Talbott rejects the Free Will Defense
against the soteriological problem of evil because (i) it is
incoherent to claim that someone could freely and irrevocably
reject God, and (ii) in any case, God would not permit such a
choice to be made because it would pain the saved. I argue that
a Molinist account escapes Talbott's objections. It is possible
both that in no world realizable by God do all persons freely
accept salvation and that God alone will endure the pain of knowledge
of the lost.
"Talbott's Universalism." Religious
Studies 27 (1991): 297-308.
See also Talbott's
Universalism Once More.
Introduction
In a pair of recently published articles,{1} Thomas Talbott has presented a carefully
constructed case for universalism. He contends that from the
principle
(P3) Necessarily, God loves a person
S (with a perfect form of love) at a time t only if God's
intention at t and every moment subsequent to t
is to do everything within his power to promote supremely worthwhile
happiness in S, provided that the actions taken are consistent
with his promoting the same kind of happiness in all others whom
he also loves
and the propositions
1. God exists
2. God is both omniscient and omnipotent
3. God loves every created person
4. God will irrevocably reject some persons and subject those
persons to everlasting punishment
a contradiction may be deduced. For given (P3),
(3) entails
5. For any created person S and time t subsequent to
the creation of S, God's intention at t is to do all that
he properly can to promote supremely worthwhile happiness in
S.
But (4) appears to entail
6. There is a person S and a time t subsequent to the
creation of S such that it is not God's intention at t
to do all that be properly can to promote supremely worthwhile
happiness in S.
But (5) and (6) are flatly contradictory.
Talbott considers three responses to this argument, which
he calls "hard-hearted theism," "moderately conservative
theism," and "biblical theism." I take it that
these labels are intended to be somewhat facetious. For according
to Talbott, "biblical theism" is universalism, which
rejects (4) or any variant thereof. "So far as I can tell,"
he asserts, "not a single passage in the Bible would require
a believer to accept such a doctrine [as hell] and the whole
thrust of the New Testament is inconsistent with it . . . ."{2} Although the New Testament
contains frequent references to hell, Talbott apparently takes
such passages to refer to a merely temporary state of the unrighteous
in the afterlife, not to a permanent state. In essence, he maintains
that biblical theism teaches some version of the doctrine of
purgatory, rather than the doctrine of hell. But such a claim
seems preposterous. What will Talbott do with the assertion of
Paul, for example, that God deems it just to inflict "vengeance
upon those who do not know God and upon those who do not obey
the gospel of our Lord Jesus. They shall suffer the punishment
of eternal destruction and exclusion from the presence of the
Lord and from the glory of his might" (II Thess. 1.6-9)?{3} Although one might perhaps
dispute whether permanent punishment or permanent annihilation
of unbelievers is here contemplated,{4}
there can be no reasonable doubt that the fate of the wicked
is everlasting. If Talbott's argument is cogent, therefore, it
is not merely conservative theism which is inconsistent: it is
biblical theism itself which involves a self-contradiction. Talbott's
argument is one more version of what I have elsewhere called
the soteriological problem of evil.{5}
Now what Talbott labels "moderately conservative theism"--but
which I prefer to call "the Free Will Defense"--would
escape the contradiction by asserting that what Talbott calls
"the Rejection Hypothesis" is at least possibly true:
(RH) Some persons will, despite God's best efforts to save
them, freely and irrevocably reject God and thus separate themselves
from God forever.
In response to this rejoinder, Talbott argues that (RH) is
not possibly true. He provides two reasons for this conviction:
(i) the choice specified in (RH) is incoherent, and (ii) even
if such a choice were coherent, necessarily God would not permit
it. In his defense of these two claims, Talbott rejects the Molinist
position on these issues as necessarily false, and it is on his
arguments against the Molinist version of the Free Will Defense
that I wish to focus.
Is irrevocable rejection of salvation logically coherent?
Talbott contends that given
(D1) For any sinner S and time t,
S finally rejects God forever at t if, and only if, (a)
S freely resolves at t never to be reconciled to God and
(b) there is nothing both within God's power to do and
consistent with the interest of all other created persons that
would (weakly) bring it about, either at t or subsequent
to t, that S freely repents of S's sin and is thereby
reconciled to God,
(RH) entails
7. There exists at least one sinner S such that nothing God
can properly do would bring it about that S freely repents of
S's sin.
In passing it is perhaps worthwhile to note that (D1)
seems a bit too strong: S need not resolve at
t never to be reconciled to God in order for his
rejection to be in fact final. On the contrary, he may kid himself
into thinking that his rejection is merely for the present, that
later he shall appropriate God's salvation, unaware that because
(b) is true he has forfeited his salvation forever. Fortunately
nothing in Talbott's argument depends on this point.
Rather Talbott regards (7) as logically impossible. He interprets
(7) to mean that ". . . no action God might perform, no
punishment he might administer, no revelation he might impart
. . . would bring about repentance in S."{6} But such an interpretation of (7) is mistaken.
For (7) specifies that God's options are limited to what He can
properly do, and from (D1) we learn
that this entails that such actions be consistent with the interest
of all other created persons. But as I have attempted to explain
in the piece referred to above,{7}
it is possible that even if for every created person S there
is a set of circumstances C in which S affirmatively responds
to God's grace and is saved, it does not follow that there is
a compossible set of circumstances in which all created persons
are saved. It may be a tragic fact of the matter, for example,
that Joe, Jr. will freely respond to God's grace and be saved
only if his father Joe, Sr. failed to do so. The matter is even
more difficult than that, however: for even if S1
would in C1 freely accept God's offer
of salvation and S2 would in C2
freely accept God's offer of salvation and C1
and C2 are compossible, it still does
not follow that in (C1-C2)
S1 would freely accept God's offer of
salvation nor that in (C1-C2)
S2 would freely accept it. Hence, it is
simply irrelevant whether it seems intuitively possible that
God could in some possible world or other win a free affirmative
response to His grace on the part of any person. It is possible
that in every world realizable by God, some persons irrevocably
reject God. Hence, Talbott's task of proving that (7) is broadly
logically impossible seems hopeless.
This consideration alone undercuts Talbott's argument for
point (i), for we see that even if the sort of choice he envisions
(to be explained below) is logically incoherent, that fact is
irrelevant, since neither (RH) nor (7) depends upon the possibility
of any such choice being made. It is possible that those who
are lost would have responded to God's salvific grace had they
been in other circumstances (such as receiving greater punishment
or revelation), but these may not have been circumstances which
God could properly bring about. Of course, in any circumstances
in which an individual finds himself, the Molinist holds that
God imparts sufficient grace for salvation and wills that such
a person respond affirmatively to it, so that God is neither
unjust nor unloving toward those who reject His grace and are
lost.
In the interest of theodicy, however, I cannot resist saying
a bit more. Not only is the above view obviously possible,
but it also seems quite plausible to me as well. When one reflects
on all the complexities involved in a world, it does not seem
surprising that there should be no feasible worlds available
to God in which all persons are freely saved (unless, perhaps,
those worlds are radically deficient in other respects, say,
by having only a handful of people in them). It may well be the
case that for some people the degree of revelation that would
have to be imparted to them in order to secure their salvation
would have to be so stunning that their freedom to disobey would
be effectively removed (cf. Talbott's own remark that ".
. . a degree of ambiguity, separation, and blindness is an essential
element in the process by which God creates a free, independent,
and rational agent"{8}).
The notion that some sinners shall finally repent under the prolonged
rigors of purgatory smacks of recantation under torture, and
we all know how likely it is that such professions are voluntary
or sincere. It seems more likely that sinners under God's punishment
will grow even harder in their hearts and more determined in
their hatred of Him for treating them thus. The idea that God
"jumps starts" sinners by repeatedly removing them
from their bondage and setting them on their course again until
they go right might well strike us as manipulative and disrespectful
of their freedom.{9}
Thus, I think it is not at all obvious that there are significant,
feasible worlds in which all persons freely come to know God's
salvation.
Let us proceed, however, to examine why Talbott thinks that
no one can irrevocably reject God's grace despite God's best
efforts to save them. To make a clear-sighted rejection of salvation
is to freely choose eternal misery for oneself. But this raises
the question: "What could possibly qualify as a motive for
such a choice? As long as any ignorance, or deception, or bondage
to desire remains, it is open to God to transform a sinner without
interfering with human freedom; but once all ignorance and deception
and bondage to desire is removed, so that a person is 'free'
to choose, there can no longer be any motive for choosing eternal
misery for oneself."{10}
Now the question being raised here by Talbott is whether it
is broadly logically possible that some creaturely individual
essences suffer from what I have, in the article mentioned above,
called transworld damnation, that is to say, the property
possessed by an essence if and only if the exemplification of
that essence freely rejects God's grace and so is lost in every
world feasible for God in which that exemplification exists.{11} Talbott rejects this
idea as "deeply incoherent" because for any person
S there are feasible worlds "in which God undermines (over
time) every possible motive that S might have for rejecting him."{12}
But is it not at least possible that the motive for
rejecting God is the will to self-autonomy, the stubborn refusal
to submit one's will to that of another? Thus Milton's Satan,
vanquished from heaven into the abyss of hell, rages against
God:
What though the field be lost?
All is not lost--the unconquerable will,
And study of revenge, immortal hate,
And courage never to submit or yield:
And what is else not to be overcome?
That glory never shall his wrath or might
Extort from me.
. . . .
Farewell, happy fields,
Where joy forever dwells! hail, horrors! hail
Infernal world! and though profoundest Hell,
Receive thy new possessor--one who brings
A mind not to be changed by place or time.
The mind is its own place, and in itself
Can make a Heaven of Hell, a Hell of Heaven.
What matter where, if I be still the same,
And what I should be, all but less than he
Whom thunder hath made greater? Here at least
We shall be free; th' Almighty hath not built
Here for his envy, will not drive us hence:
Here we may reign secure; and, in my choice,
To reign is worth ambition, though in Hell:
Better to reign in Hell than serve in Heaven.{13}
Is it not possible that some human persons will similarly
insist with William Ernest Henley:
It matters not how strait the gate,
How charged with punishments the scroll,
I am the master of my fate:
I am the captain of my soul.{14}
Even omnipotent love can be spurned if that love requires
worship and submission of one's will. Talbott might insist that
such a motivation is irrational--but so what? Is it not possible
that the will to self-autonomy be so strong in some persons that
they will act irrationally in preferring self-rule to God's rule?
Indeed, does there need to be any motivation for such rebellion
at all? Is it not possible that some persons would deliberately
choose evil for its own sake? In his short story "The Black
Cat," Poe describes the springs of a man's brutality to
the family pet:
And then came, as if to my final and irrevocable overthrow,
the spirit of PERVERSENESS. Of this spirit philosophy takes no
account. Yet I am not more sure that my soul loves, than I am
that perverseness is one of the primitive impulses of the human
heart--one of the indivisible primary faculties, or sentiments,
which give direction to the character of Man. Who has not, a
hundred times, found himself committing a vile or a silly action,
for no other reason than because he knows he should not?
Have we not a perpetual inclination, in the teeth of our best
judgment, to violate that which is Law, merely because
we understand it to be such? This spirit of perverseness, I say,
came to my final overthrow. It was this unfathomable longing
of the soul to vex itself--to offer violence to its own
nature--to do wrong for the wrong's sake only--that urged me
to continue and finally to consummate the injury I had inflicted
upon the unoffending brute. One morning, in cool blood, I slipped
a noose about its neck and hung it to the limb of a tree;--hung
it with the tears streaming from my eyes, and with the bitterest
remorse at my heart;--hung it because I knew that it had
loved me, and because I felt it had given me no reason
of offense; hung it because I knew that in so doing I
was committing a sin--a deadly sin that would so jeopardize my
immortal soul as to place it--if such a thing were possible--even
beyond the reach of the infinite mercy of the Most Merciful and
Most Terrible God.{15}
It seems to me quite clear that the above two accounts of
human rebellion against God are logically possible, and that
short of a freedom-removing revelation of Himself, God may therefore
be unable to win the free response of some persons regardless
of the circumstances they are in. Of course, a person suffering
from transworld damnation need not be a fiend; in some worlds
he may be a very good person, perhaps very close to receiving
God's grace, but nonetheless he fails to do so under even these
circumstances. His motivations for not responding to God's offer
of salvation may be numerous and diverse in the various worlds
in which he exists; but even under the most favorable of circumstances
such as Talbott envisions it is possible that human self-will
and perversity are such that even then he will not bow the knee
to God and be saved. Nor need God repeatedly "jump start"
sinners or continually punish them in order to discover this
fact. Via His middle knowledge God could have so providentially
arranged the world that persons who do not accept His offer of
salvation in this life are only those who also would not accept
it if given a second chance or more. It is possible that only
irremediably unbelieving persons are in hell; its door is thus
locked, as Sartre opined, from the inside. In fact it is possible
that after offering sufficient grace for salvation to someone
for a time, there comes a point in a person's life after which
God no longer pursues him but gives him up to his fate, knowing
that further prevenient grace would be futile. What we come to
see, therefore, is that (P3) is not true
after all and that (3) does not therefore entail (5). On the
contrary because (RH) is possibly true, so is (4) and therefore
(6).
This seems to me once more to settle the matter; but in the
interest of theodicy I wish to add that such an account strikes
me as entirely plausible. Human evil and rebellion are so severe
that it seems quite plausible to me that some persons should
freely and irrevocably reject God despite His best efforts to
save them. It is at this point that one of the greatest weaknesses
in Talbott's theological outlook emerges: it seems to me that
he really does not have a serious doctrine of sin. I should say
that he greatly underestimates both human depravity and human
capacity to sin. Admittedly, it is insane that some people should
resist every solicitation of the Holy Spirit and every offer
of God's grace and perhaps even prefer damnation to submission
to God's will, but that is the mystery of iniquity, a measure
of the depth of human depravity. That Talbott does not fully
appreciate the Christian doctrine of sin is evident from his
comments on the self-collapse of evil:
. . . over a long period of time, moral evil inevitably destroys
itself. On this picture, the root of all moral evil as well as
the ultimate source of human misery is separation from God (and
from others); and the motive for moral evil is the illusion
that we can benefit ourselves at the expense of others. So the
more we separate ourselves from God, the more miserable we become,
and the more miserable we become, the more likely we are to shatter
the illusion that makes moral evil possible. Many of us can,
of course, continue to deceive ourselves for many years, perhaps
even for the duration of our short seventy years or so in this
life . . . . But in the end, according to the New Testament picture,
moral evil will always destroy itself and thus becomes its own
corrective.{16}
This is the picture of the New Testament? What has become
of Christus Victor? It is God in Christ who has entered
our hopeless estate to conquer sin, death, and the devil. Without
God's supernatural grace, our separation from God would never
be bridged; we should go from bad to worse. But on Talbott's
view, Satan himself must eventually be saved. I am not saying
that it is impossible to integrate the cross into Talbott's theology,
and perhaps he has expressed himself poorly here; but the very
fact that he can speak of moral evil as self-destructive
and self-corrective rather than as divinely destroyed
and corrected suggests that he lacks any profound appreciation
of human sin and willful estrangement from God.
In summary, Talbott's first argument for the logical impossibility
of (RH) fails because (i) he has not demonstrated that it is
logically incoherent that some persons would freely reject God
regardless of what freedom-preserving circumstances they were
in, and (ii) he has not demonstrated that it is logically necessary
that such persons exist in every feasible world of free creatures
in order that all worlds of free creatures which are feasible
for God are worlds in which some people freely reject God's grace
and are lost.
Is it logically necessary that God prevent irrevocable
rejection of salvation?
Talbott argues that even if the choice specified in (RH) were
coherent, God would necessarily prevent anyone from making such
a choice. In particular, if God could not have populated a universe
with free agents none of whom are irredeemable (in the sense
that they freely reject Him forever) and God knew this fact via
His middle knowledge, then He would have faced a catastrophe
of such proportions that He would have had no choice but to prevent
it.
Talbott begins by asking whether it is possible that God was
powerless to create a universe of free agents all of whom are,
of their own free will, eventually reconciled to Him. We have
seen that the Molinist could respond that no such world is feasible
for God. Even if there are circumstances in which each person
would freely be reconciled to God and even if various sets of
such are compossible, it still does not follow that in such composite
sets of circumstances, all of the persons would freely be reconciled
to God. It is possible that there is no world feasible for God
in which all persons are freely reconciled to Him. Talbott unfortunately
misexpresses this position in the following way:
Some created persons will freely enter into everlasting fellowship
with God only if others experience everlasting damnation and
therefore everlasting separation from God. For it is at least
possible . . . that God faces this dreadful reality: He must
bring about (weakly) the damnation of some in order that he might
bring about (weakly) the salvation of others; it is possible,
in other words, that the company of the redeemed in heaven will
remain faithful only because they have seen what happens to those
who do not remain faithful.{17}
This last statement is completely erroneous, giving the impression
that the reprobate are the instrumentality by which God secures
the perseverance of the redeemed. But the theory implies no such
thing; the redeemed could be completely unaware that there even
are any reprobate, but it jut happens to be the case that in
all feasible worlds a number of people freely reject God's grace
and are lost. Thus, the Molinist could agree with Talbott that
". . . a loving God would never engineer the damnation of
some of those he could have saved . . . in order to save others."{18} The fact that some
people freely reject God's grace and are lost could be simply
the unfortunate concomitant of many people's freely accepting
God's grace and being saved.
Now Talbott does not deny that God, in actualizing such a
world, is neither unjust nor unloving toward those who are lost
in such a world (since He supplies sufficient grace for salvation
to all persons). But, Talbott argues, this defense of the compatibility
of God's existence and particularism "has neglected one
all-important point: that the lost, simply by being lost forever,
would bring intolerable suffering, not only into their own lives,
but into the lives of others as well."{19} What Talbott has in mind here is the
"irreparable harm" done to the redeemed who must suffer
the agony of seeing their loved ones who have rejected God's
grace eternally damned.{20}
They cannot be supremely happy in heaven so long as they know
that those whom they love are eternally tormented in hell. Moreover,
if God could have saved their loved ones but did not, then the
redeemed cannot truly love and worship God, since they must disapprove
of what God has done. Talbott draws three conclusions: (i) ".
. . blessedness in one person requires blessedness in others,
and one person's ruin implies the ruin of others;" (ii)
". . . the misery of those in hell would inevitably undermine
the blessedness of those in heaven;" and (iii) ". .
. neither the salvation of one person, nor that of a given combination
of persons, could possibly require, in virtue of certain true
'counterfactuals of freedom,' the damnation of other persons."{21}
Point (iii), admits Talbott, depends on what we mean by salvation.
So he proposes as a partial definition:
(D3) God brings salvation to a sinner
S only if, among other things, God brings it about (weakly) that
the following conditions obtain: (a) that S is reconciled
to God and in a state of supreme happiness, (b) that S
is filled with love for others and therefore desires the good
for all other created persons, and (c) that there is no
fact F such that (i) S is ignorant of F and (ii)
were S not ignorant of F, then S would have been unable
to experience supreme happiness.{22}
On the basis of (D3) Talbott maintains
that a Molinist position like
8. God has actualized a world containing an optimal balance
between saved and unsaved, and those who are unsaved suffer from
transworld damnation
is not even possibly true. For ". . . the eternal damnation
of a single person would undermine the salvation of all others;
so an optimal balance between saved and unsaved could not possibly
include any who are unsaved."{23}
In point of fact, continues Talbott, nothing of substance really
hangs on (D3):
In a nutshell, the argument is this. God necessarily wills
that each created person should eventually achieve a special
kind of blessedness: a kind that (a) exists only when
one is filled with love for others and (b) would survive
even a full disclosure of facts about the world. But such blessedness
is simply not possible in a world in which some persons are eternally
damned and therefore eternally miserable.{24}
The bottom line is that if God, via His middle knowledge,
knows logically prior to His creative decree which persons or
combinations thereof are irredeemable, then He would simply refrain
from creating those persons. Instead He would restrict Himself
to those feasible worlds in which all persons freely find salvation.
If there are no such feasible worlds, then God would either refrain
from creating any persons at all or He would interfere with human
freedom and set his sights on goods that do not require free
will."{25} But
in no case would He create worlds in which even a single person
rejects Him and is lost, lest the supreme happiness of the redeemed
be thereby undermined.
Now when one recalls that Talbott has set himself the heavy
task of proving that the Molinist position is not even broadly
logically possible, then I think it is evident that he has fallen
short of his goal. For one could agree that knowledge of loved
ones' damnation would undermine the supreme happiness of the
redeemed, but maintain that it is possible that the redeemed
in heaven have no such knowledge. Perhaps God obliterates from
their minds any knowledge of lost persons so that they experience
no pangs of remorse for them. Talbott objects, "He could,
of course, always deceive me concerning the fate of my child,
producing within me a kind of blissful ignorance; but on the
Christian view, God is incapable of such immoral deception."{26} But I see no reason
to think such shielding of His redeemed people from this painful
knowledge is immoral deception. We can all think of cases in
which we shield persons from knowledge which would be painful
for them and which they do not need to have, and, far from doing
something immoral, we are, in so sparing them, exemplifying the
virtue of mercy. In fact, I see God's taking on Himself alone
the suffering of knowing the state of the lost as a beautiful
extension of Christ's suffering on the cross. Alvin Plantinga
has written,
Some theologians claim that God cannot suffer. I believe they
are wrong. God's capacity for suffering, I believe, is proportional
to his greatness; it exceeds our capacity for suffering in the
same measure as his capacity for knowledge exceeds ours. Christ
was prepared to endure the agonies of hell itself; and God, the
Lord of the universe, was prepared to endure the suffering consequent
upon his son's humiliation and death. He was prepared to accept
this suffering in order to overcome sin, and death, and the evils
that afflict our world, and to confer on us a life more glorious
than we can imagine.{27}
In shielding His redeemed people from the painful knowledge
of the estate of the damned and bearing it Himself alone, God
extends the suffering of the cross into eternity. The terrible
secret of the condition of the lost is buried for eternity deep
within the breast of God, a burden whose gravity only He can
fully feel and yet which He willingly takes upon Himself in order
that He might bring free creatures into the supreme and unalloyed
joy of fellowship with Himself.
In any case, we need not appeal to God's action in expunging
such knowledge from the minds of the redeemed. It is possible
that the very experience itself of being in the immediate presence
of Christ (cf. the beatific vision) will simply drive from the
minds of His redeemed any awareness of the lost in hell. So overwhelming
will be His presence and the love and joy which it inspires that
the knowledge of the damned will be banished from the consciousness
of God's people. In such a case, the redeemed would still have
such knowledge, but they would never be conscious of it
and so never pained by it. Such a solution seems obviously possible;
indeed, I should go so far as to say that it is quite plausible
as well. Thus, contrary to Talbott, (i) blessedness in the redeemed
does not require blessedness in all persons; (ii) the misery
of the lost would not inevitably undermine the blessedness of
the saved; and (iii) the salvation of any combination of persons
may, in virtue of certain true counterfactuals of freedom, only
be feasible if there are a number of persons who are lost.
But what, then, of (D3)? If we adopt
as our possible solution to Talbott's dilemma the view that Christ's
immediate presence drives from consciousness the knowledge of
the condition of the lost, then all the conditions of salvation
specified in (D3) are fulfilled. For the
redeemed may know that their loved ones are lost, but may not
be conscious of it. Hence, the Molinist solution specified in
(8) is possible. Of course, Talbott could amend clause (c)
of (D3) by substituting for "ignorant"
something like "unaware" or "unconscious."
But then we are surely justified in doubting that clause (c)
is a necessary condition of salvation. So long as S is
supremely happy, how is his salvation annulled by the fact that
if he were aware of F, then he would not
be supremely happy? Nothing seems to justify this condition either
philosophically or biblically. How then is it incumbent on the
Christian theist? Although Talbott thinks (D3)
is inessential to his argument, the misgivings I have expressed
about (c) also apply to clause (b) in his nutshell
statement of the argument. I see no reason, biblical or philosophical,
to think that God necessarily wills the special kind of blessedness
which Talbott's argument requires.
In sum, it is possible that in the moment logically prior
to His decree to create, God knew via His middle knowledge either
that there were no feasible worlds in which all persons are freely
saved or that any such feasible worlds possessed other outweighing
deficiencies. In choosing to actualize a world, God determined
to offer sufficient grace for salvation, not only to those who
He knew would accept it, but even to those who He knew would
reject it. Since He knew that due to the light of His presence
to the redeemed in heaven, the misery of the lost would not undermine
the blessedness of the redeemed, He was not obliged to refrain
from creation nor to set His sights on lesser goods that do not
require free will, but could create a world in which a great
multitude from every tongue and tribe and people and nation should
freely come to receive His grace and so enter into the boundless
joy of His fellowship forever. The pain of the awareness of the
state of the damned, persons for whom Christ died and who stubbornly
resisted the drawing of the Holy Spirit, remains known to God
alone.
Conclusion
A Molinist version of the Free Will Defense certainly seems
to be logically consistent and therefore escapes Talbott's statement
of the soteriological problem of evil. It is possible that in
no realizable world do all persons freely accept salvation, since
it is possible that either the circumstances in which each person
would be saved are not compossible or that if they are,
in the composite circumstances not every person would freely
accept salvation. Moreover, it is possible that some persons
out of self-will or perversity would freely reject God no matter
what the circumstances He placed them in. The tragic fact that
every world feasible for God is one involving persons who are
lost would not force Him to refrain from creation or to annul
creaturely freedom lest the blessedness of the saved be undermined,
for it is possible that the reality of lost persons is a fact
which He alone shall endure for eternity.{28}
Endnotes
{1}Thomas
Talbott, "The Doctrine of Everlasting Punishment,"
Faith and Philosophy 7 (1990): 19-42; idem, "Providence,
Freedom, and Human Destiny," Religious Studies 26
(1990): 227-45.
{2}Talbott, "Everlasting
Punishment," pp. 19-20.
{3}It is not open
to Talbott to respond here as he does to Swinburne's citation
of Matt. 25.45 that the word for punishment (kolasiV)
always refers in Greek secular literature to remedial punishment
and that one may not derive doctrine from the incidentals of
a parable. For Paul is teaching doctrine, and his words for vengeance
and punishment are edikhsiV and dikh, which carry the sense of divine retribution
and revenge. Moreover, Talbott's claim about the meaning of kolasiV is false and in any case somewhat
irrelevant, since kolasiV is used
in Judaeo-Christian literature for punishment which is non-remedial,
e.g. IV Macc. 8:9 concerning severe punishments preceding
execution, II Cl. 6.7 concerning eternal punishment from which
there is no salvation, Dg. 9.2 concerning punishment and death
as the reward of the unrighteous (Theological Dictionary of
the New Testament, ed. Gerhard Kittel, s.v. "kolazw,
kolasiV" by Johannes Schneider).
One need not be a Greek scholar to recognize that the "eternal
punishment" (kolasiV aiwnioV
) spoken of by Jesus cannot be remedial, since taking eternity
to be purged of one's sin does not differ from never being purged
of it! As for Talbott's hermeneutical point, the contrast between
eternal punishment and eternal life features prominently in the
parable and fits the context of divine judgement in the whole
discourse, echoes Old Testament teaching (Dan. 12.2), and is
straightforwardly affirmed by Jesus elsewhere (John 5.28-29;
Mark 9.48).
{4}See brief discussion
and references in John Wenham, The Enigma of Evil: Can We
Believe in the Goodness of God? (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Zondervan:
1985).
{5}William Lane Craig,
"'No Other Name': A Middle Knowledge Perspective on the
Exclusivity of Salvation through Christ," Faith and Philosophy
6 (1989): 172-88.
{6}Talbott, "Everlasting
Punishment," pp. 36-37.
{7}Craig, "'No
Other Name'," pp. 172-88.
{8}Talbott, "Human
Destiny," p. 236.
{9}A point made effectively
by Larry Lacy, "John Hick on Universal Salvation,"
paper presented at the Eastern Division meeting of the Society
of Christian Philosophers, University of Dayton, April 7-9, 1988.
{10}Talbott, "Everlasting
Punishment," p. 37; cf. idem, "Human Destiny,"
p. 228: "If God is the ultimate source of human happiness
and separation from God can bring only greater and greater misery
into one's life, as Christians have traditionally believed, then
why should anyone want to reject God?"
{11}Craig, "'No
Other Name'," p. 184. Talbott cannot mean by God's best
efforts what He can properly do in the actual world, for we have
already seen that what God can properly do to win some sinner's
repentance may be far less than the sort of optimal circumstances
which Talbott envisions. What Talbott is speaking of is a choice
to reject God's grace irrevocably under the most conducive of
circumstances for repentance. The question is whether there is
what Molinists call "congruent grace" for every free
creature God could possibly create.
{12}Talbott, "Human
Destiny," p. 237.
{13}John Milton,
Paradise Lost, ed. with an Introduction by Northrup Frye
(New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1962), Bk. I. 105-111,
249-263; pp. 8, 12.
{14}William Ernest
Henley, "Invictus," in Modern Verse, rev. ed.,
ed. Oscar Williams (New York: Pocket Books, 1958), p. 111.
{15}Edgar Allan
Poe, "The Black Cat," in Complete Stories and Poems
of Edgar Allan Poe (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1966),
p. 65.
{16}Talbott, "Human
Destiny," p. 244. Cf. idem, "Everlasting Punishment,"
p. 39.
"The more one freely rebels against God, the more miserable
and tormented one becomes; and the more miserable and tormented
one becomes, the more incentive one has to repent of one's sin
and to give up one's rebellious attitudes. But more than that,
the consequences of sin are themselves a means of revelation;
they reveal the true meaning of separation and enable us to see
through the very self-deception that makes evil choices possible
in the first place. We may think we can promote our own interest
at the expense of others and that our selfish attitudes are compatible
with enduring happiness, but we cannot act upon such an illusion,
at least not for a long period of time, without shattering it
to pieces. So in a sense, all roads have the same destination,
the end of reconciliation, but some are longer and windier than
others."
The view expressed here is clearly Pelagian and obviates the
need for any gracious action of God at all in drawing sinners
to Himself. It grossly underestimates the lostness and hopelessness
of sinners apart from God.
{17}Talbott, "Human
Destiny," p. 235.
{18}Ibid., p. 238.
{19}Ibid., p. 237.
{20}Ibid., p. 238;
cf. idem, "Everlasting Punishment," pp. 38-39.
{21}Talbott, "Human
Destiny," p. 239.
{22}Ibid.
{23}Ibid., p. 240.
{24}Ibid.
{25}Ibid., p. 241;
cf. p. 245.
{26}Talbott, "Human
destiny," pp. 237-38.
{27}Alvin Plantinga,
"Self-Profile," in Alvin Plantinga, ed. James
Tomberlin and Peter Van Inwagen, Profiles 5 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel,
1985), p. 36.
{28}I am indebted
to Thomas Talbott for his remarks on the first draft of this
article.
Copyright (C) William Lane Craig. All Rights Reserved.
Copyright/Reproduction Limitations
This data file/document is the sole property of William
Lane Craig, It may not be altered or edited in any way. It
may be reproduced only in its entirety for circulation as "freeware,"
without charge. All reproductions of this data file and/or document
must contain the copyright notice (i.e., Copyright (c) 1996
William Lane Craig) and this Copyright/Reproduction Limitations
notice.
This data file/document may not be used without the permission
of William Lane Craig for resale or the enhancement of
any other product sold.
William Lane Craig
c/o Leadership University
3440 Sojourn Drive, Suite 200
Carrollton, TX 75006
U. S. A.
Return to the
Protestant Apologetics and Theology page
|